Silencing the past: power and the production of history
Michel-Rolph Trouillot c2015 © Beacon Press
Chapter 1: The Power in the Story
Theorizing Ambiguity and Tracking Power (p. 22-30)
History is always produced in a specific historical context. Historical
actors are also narrators, and vice versa.
The affirmation that narratives are always produced in history and the overlap between process and narrative. Thus, although this book is primarily about history as knowledge and narrative, 27
it fully embraces the ambiguity inherent in the two sides of historicity.
History, as social process, involves peoples in three distinct capacities:
1) as agents, or occupants of structural positions; 2) as
actors in constant interface with a context; and 3) as subjects, that
is, as voices aware of their vocality. Classical examples of what I
call agents are the strata and sets to which people belong, such as
class and status, or the roles associated with these. Workers, slaves,
mothers are agents. 28 An analysis of slavery can explore the sociocultural,
political, economic, and ideological structures that define
such positions as slaves and masters.
By actors, I mean the bundle of capacities that are specific in
time and space in ways that both their existence and their understanding
rest fundamentally on historical particulars. A comparison
of African-American slavery in Brazil and the United States
that goes beyond a statistical table must deal with the historical
particulars that define the situations being compared. Historical
narratives address particular situations and, in that sense, they
must deal with human beings as actors. 29
But peoples are also the subjects of history the way workers are
subjects of a strike: they define the very terms under situations
can be described. Consider a strike as a historical event from
a strictly narrative viewpoint, that is, without the interventions
that we usually put under such labels as interpretation or
explanation. There is no way we can describe a strike without making
the subjective capacities of the workers a central part of the
description. 30 Stating their absence from the workplace is certainly
not enough. We need to state that they collectively reached
the decision to stay at home on what was supposed to be a regular
working day. We need to add that they collectively acted upon
That decision. But even such a description, which takes into account
the workers' position as actors, is not a competent description
of a strike. Indeed, there are a few other contexts in which
such a description could account for something else. Workers
could have decided: if the snowfall exceeds ten inches tonight,
None of us will come to work tomorrow. If we accept scenarios of
manipulation or errors of interpretation among the actors, the
possibilities become limitless. Thus, beyond dealing with the
workers as actors, a competent narrative of a strike needs to claim
access to the workers as purposeful subjects aware of their own
voices. It needs their voice(s) in the first person or, at least, it needs
to paraphrase that first person. The narrative must give us a hint
of both the reasons why the workers refuse to work and the objective
they think they are pursuing-even if that objective is
limited to the voicing of protest. To put it most simply, a strike is
a strike only if the workers think that they are striking. Their subjectivity
is an integral part of the event and of any satisfactory
description of that event.
Workers work much more often than they strike, but the capacity
to strike is never fully removed from the condition of workers.
In other words, peoples are not always subjects constantly confronting
history as some academics would wish, but the capacity
upon which they act to become subjects is always part of their
condition. This subjective capacity ensures confusion because it
makes human beings doubly historical or, more properly, fully
historical. It engages them simultaneously in the sociohistorical
process and in narrative constructions about that process. The
embracing of this ambiguity, which is inherent in what I call the
two sides of historicity, is the first choice of this book.
The second choice of this book is a concrete focus on the process
of historical production rather than an abstract concern for the
nature of history. The search for the nature of history has led us
to deny ambiguity and either to demarcate precisely and at all
times the dividing line between historical process and historical
knowledge or to conflate at all times historical process and historical
narrative. Thus between the mechanically "realist" and
naively "constructivist" extremes, there is the more serious task
of determining not what history is-a hopeless goal if phrased in
essentialist terms-but how history works. For what history is
changes with time and place or, better said, history reveals itself
only through the production of specific narratives. What matters
most are the process and conditions of production of such narratives.
Only a focus on that process can uncover the ways in
which the two sides of historicity intertwine in a particular context.
Only through that overlap can we discover the differential
exercise of power that makes some narratives possible and silences
others.
Tracking power requires a richer view of historical production
than most theorists acknowledge. We cannot exclude in advance
any of the actors who participate in the production of history
or any of the sites where that production may occur. Next to professional
historians we discover artisans of different kinds, unpaid
or unrecognized field laborers who augment, deflect, or reorganize
the work of the professionals as politicians, students, fiction
writers, filmmakers, and participating members of the public. In
so doing, we gain a more complex view of academic history itself,
since we do not consider professional historians the sole participants
in its production.
This more comprehensive view expands the chronological
boundaries of the production process. We can see that process as
both starting earlier and going on later than most theorists admit.
The process does not stop with the last sentence of a professional
historian since the public is quite likely to contribute to history if
only by adding its own readings to-and about-the scholarly
productions. More important, perhaps, since the overlap between
history as social process and history as knowledge is fluid,
participants in any event may enter into the production of a narrative
about that event before the historian as such reaches the
scene. In fact, the historical narrative within which an actual
event fits could precede that event itself, at least in theory, but
perhaps also in practice. Marshall Sahlins suggests that the Hawaiians
read their encounter with Captain Cook as the chronicle
of a death foretold. But such exercises are not limited to the peoples
without historians. How much do narratives of the end of the
Cold War fit into a prepackaged history of capitalism in knightly
armor? William Lewis suggests that one of Ronald Reagan's political
strengths was his capacity to inscribe his presidency into a
prepackaged narrative about the United States. And an overall
sketch of world historical production through time suggests that
professional historians alone do not set the narrative framework
into which their stories fit. Most often, someone else has already
entered the scene and set the cycle of silences. 31
Does this expanded view still allow pertinent generalizations
about the production of the historical narrative? The answer to
this question is an unqualified yes, if we agree that such generalizations
enhance our understanding of specific practices but do
not provide blueprints that practice will supposedly follow or
illustrate.
Silences enter the process of historical production at four crucial
moments: the moment of fact creation (the making of sources);
the moment of fact assembly (the making of archives); the moment
of fact retrieval (the making of narratives); and the moment
of retrospective significance (the making of history in the final
instance).
These moments are conceptual tools, second-level abstractions
of processes that feed on each other. As such, they are not meant
to provide a realistic description of the making of any individual
narrative. Rather, they help us understand why not all silences
are equal and why they cannot be addressed-or redressed-in
the same manner. To put it differently, any historical narrative is
a particular bundle of silences, the result of a unique process, and
the operation required to deconstruct these silences will vary accordingly.
The strategies deployed in this book reflect these variations.
Each of the narratives treated in the next three chapters combines
diverse types of silences. In each case, these silences crisscross or
accumulate over time to produce a unique mixture. In each case
I use a different approach to reveal the conventions and the tensions
within that mixture.
In chapter 2, I sketch the image of a former slave turned colonel,
now a forgotten figure of the Haitian Revolution. The evidence
required to tell his story was available in the corpus I studied, in
spite of the poverty of the sources. I only reposition that evidence
to generate a new narrative. My alternative narrative, as it develops,
reveals the silences that buried, until now, the story of the
colonel.
The general silencing of the Haitian Revolution by Western
historiography is the subject of chapter 3. That silencing also is
due to uneven power in the production of sources, archives, and
narratives. But if I am correct that this revolution was unthinkable
as it happened, the insignificance of the story is already inscribed
in the sources, regardless of what else they reveal. There
are no new facts here; not even neglected ones. Here, I have to make
the silences speak for themselves. I do so by juxtaposing the climate
of the times, the writings of historians on the revolution itself,
and narratives of world history where the effectiveness of
the original silence becomes fully visible.
The discovery of America, the theme of chapter 4, provided me
with yet another combination, thus compelling yet a third strategy.
Here was an abundance of both sources and narratives. Until
1992, there was even a sense-although forged and recent-of
global agreement on the significance of Columbus's first trip. The
main tenets of historical writings were inflected and bolstered
through public celebrations that seemed to reinforce this significance.
Within this wide-open corpus, silences are produced not so
much by an absence of facts or interpretations as through conflicting
appropriations of Columbus's persona. Here, I do not suggest
a new reading of the same story, as I do in chapter 2, or even
alternative interpretations, as in chapter 3. Rather, I show how
the alleged agreement about Columbus actually masks a history
of conflicts. The methodological exercise culminates in a narrative
about the competing appropriations of the discovery. Silences
appear in the interstices of the conflicts between previous interpreters.
The production of a historical narrative cannot be studied, therefore,
through a mere chronology of its silences. The moments I distinguish
here overlap in real time. As heuristic devices, they only
crystallize aspects of historical production that best expose when
and where power gets into the story.
But even this phrasing is misleading if it suggests that power
exists outside the story and can therefore be blocked or excised.
Power is constitutive of the story. Tracking power through various
"moments" simply helps emphasize the fundamentally processual
character of historical production, to insist that what
history is matters less than how history works; that power itself
works together with history; and that the historians' claimed
political preferences have little influence on most of the actual
practices of power. A warning from Foucault is helpful: "I don't
believe that the question of 'who exercises power?' can be resolved
unless that other question 'how does it happen?' is resolved
at the same time." 32
Power does not enter the story once and for all, but at different
times and from different angles. It precedes the narrative proper,
contributes to its creation and to its interpretation. Thus, it remains
pertinent even if we can imagine a totally scientific history,
even if we relegate the historians' preferences and stakes to
a separate, post-descriptive phase. In history, power begins at the
source.
The play of power in the production of alternative narratives
begins with the joint creation of facts and sources for at least two
reasons. First, facts are never meaningless: indeed, they become
facts only because they matter in some sense, however minimal.
Second, facts are not created equal: the production of traces is
always also the creation of silences. Some occurrences are noted
from the start; others are not. Some are engraved in individual or
collective bodies; others are not. Some leave physical markers;
others do not. What happened leaves traces, some of which are
quite concrete-buildings, dead bodies, censuses, monuments,
diaries, political boundaries-that limit the range and significance
of any historical narrative. This is one of many reasons why
not any fiction can pass for history: the materiality of the sociohistorical
process (historicity 1) sets the stage for future historical
narratives (historicity 2).us take it for granted. It does not imply that facts are meaningless
objects waiting to be discovered under some timeless seal but
The materiality of this first moment is so obvious that some of
rather, more modestly, that history begins with bodies and artifacts:
living brains, fossils, texts, buildings. 33
The bigger the material mass, the more easily it entraps us: mass
graves and pyramids bring history closer while they make us feel
small. A castle, a fort, a battlefield, a church, all these things bigger
than we that we infuse with the reality of past lives, seem to
speak of an immensity of which we know little except that we are
part of it. Too solid to be unmarked, too conspicuous to be can-
did, they embody the ambiguities of history. They give us the
power to touch it, but not that to hold it firmly in our hands hence
the mystery of their battered walls. We suspect that their
concreteness hides secrets so deep that no revelation may fully
dissipate their silences. We imagine the lives under the mortar,
but how do we recognize the end of a bottomless silence?